Thursday, June 28, 2018

The Christian ideal has not been tried and found wanting. It has been…

The Christian ideal has not been tried and found wanting. It has been found difficult; and left untried."

― G.K. Chesterton, What's Wrong with the World


キリスト教の理想は試されて、物足りないと感じられたわけではない。それは実践するのが生易しいものではないことが判明し、試行せずに残された。


- G.K.チェスタートン、世界とは何が問題か


iPadから送信

Sunday, June 24, 2018

Lessons from history



It is said that the first word chosen by S. Francis X. for God is Dainichi Nyorai 大日如来(Vairocana). Probably a suggestion from Anjiro or from the people he met in Japan. Dainichi Nyorai can be translated "Cosmic (the big sun) Such-ness" or "The cosmos as-it-is". It is the representation of Buddhist emptiness and at the same time a pantheistic deity sometimes connected to Amaterasu.
When S. Francis realized the difference with God, to avoid any kind of misunderstanding, immediately changed the word in the Latin Deus (Deusu). After not so many years the word was distorted, as the report goes by malevolent Buddhist clergy,in the Japanese word "Dai-uso", meaning "big lie".
The lessons I obtain from this episode are:
  1. Not necessarily the people you are try to evangelize will help you find the best words
  2. You can make mistakes in choosing the words, and the earlier you realize that the better.
  3. All neologisms must gain the right of citizenship

After the year 1600 the word Tenshu 天主 was adopted probably by suggestion from Valignano who was in contact with Matteo Ricci in China. Ricci in the preparation of his catechism did all the work necessary to transmit in an unequivocal fashion the real meaning of the God of Christianity, which was a complete novelty in China as in Japan. The title says it all, 天主実義 "The real Meaning of the Lord of Heaven".
Lessons to be obtained
  1. evangelization is a linguistic battle field
  2. You must struggle to get the right words through to your audience. (By the way I think the level of inculturation, as far as the kanji cultures, China, Korea and Japan are concerned, reached by Ricci stand unsurpassed to this day).
"Ricci is adding another dimension to the five relationships of Confucianism among human beings (king and officials, father and son, husband and wife, brother and brother, friend and friend): the relationship between human being and their Creator."

(CHUNG-YAN JOYCE CHAN, Commands from Heaven: Mattoe Ricci's Christianity in the Eyes of Ming Confucian Officials, Missiology vol. XXXI, 3, July 2003, p. 284)

The catechism by Ricci was widely circulated and the word Tenshu is still used today in China and in Korea. In Japan it has been used until the 1960s when it was changed for the word use today namely "Kami".


iPhoneから送信

Hさん

Hさん

メールをいただきました。
音声で文書を書けることはご存知ですか。スマホですと、グーゴルのアプリで簡単です。パソコンですと何百円のマイクロフォンをつけるだけでできます。

ローマ神話とキリストの生誕の違い、というご質問ですが、違いは400もの種類があります。ここで全部書くわけにいかないので、今回とりあえず三つぐらい述べさしてもらいます。

1、キリストの生誕は毎年、世界どこででも祝われています。ディオニソスの誕生は、千何百年前から祝う人はほとんどいない。
2、キリストの生誕を祝う人の中で、神話ではないと認識している人は、何億人います。
3、キリストの生誕は神話ではないと認識している人の中で、哲学史上、最高レベルの思想家がいます。
いかがでしょうか。このような違いを否定する人は正気と言えるでしょうか。

次にパウロですが、パウロはアルマゲドンを予言した、とおっしゃるのですけれども、これは聖書のどこですか?あなたの思い違いではないでしょうか。

アルマゲドンという言葉は出てくるのは、黙示録(16、16)です。これは、パウロではない。ヨハネなんです。アルマゲドンというのは、地名です。イスラエルにある山の名前なんです。ごく最近では、それは映画のタイトルともなって、そのために日本でも知られるようになったが、それは勝手な解釈で、聖書の考えとは全く関係がない。

初代教会の人々は、世の終わりが近いと信じていました。そして、それは、起こらなかった、と。これは、聖書知らずの世間の一般的な考えでしょう。
考えてみてください。Hさんは、2118年にこの世に生きていると思いますか。私もそうでしょうけど、多分いないでしょう。そうしたら、私たちにとっては、世の終わりは近い、と言えないでしょうか。世の終わりは、神学的な専門用語で、「終末(eschatology)」といいますが、私たちの人生の終末は近いと言っても、別に何もおかしいことはない。
予言があって、そしてそれは実現しなかった。これは、聖書というよりも、ノストラダムス(ヴィキペディアとでも引いてみてください)の程度の話です。


iPhoneから送信

Monday, June 11, 2018

The Churches of Earthly Power by Russell Hittinger | Articles | First Things

The Churches of Earthly Power by Russell Hittinger | Articles | First Things

The Churches of Earthly Power

Michael Burleigh's study of European religion and politics requires us to imagine a very different Europe than the one we behold today—not the polity of bureaucrats in Brussels but a Europe of statesmen and revolutionaries who aimed at the most extravagant notions of national destiny.

Beginning with the French Revolution and running through World War I, Earthly Powers chronicles more than a century of unrelieved turmoil. No project was too big for the human mind, whether the conquest of nations, the civilizing of colonial peoples, the creation of new religions, and the invention of most every -ism worth fighting about. Auguste Comte's proposal that the earth's elliptical path be changed to a circular orbit to moderate climatic extremes was emblematic of a culture in which the state, science, and religion pledged their energies to eschatological visions. 

Burleigh's main theme is the problem of religion. Here, too, we must put out of our minds any simple notion of the kind of secularization we now see in Europe—for rather than emptying the public square of religious ideas and debates, religion flooded the newspapers, the bookstores, and the cabinets of government. Such statesmen as Gladstone and Bismarck regarded themselves as experts on matters ecclesiastical and theological, just as prelates fancied themselves as having important things to say on issues of economics and social policy. In the centuries that transpired between the religious wars of the sixteenth century and the formation of nation-states during the nineteenth, Europeans certainly had not lost their appetite for religious opinions, nor the quest for an integral relationship between religion and what Burleigh calls "earthly powers." When Pius IX issued the Syllabus of Errors in 1864, the eighty condemned propositions tell us at least as much about the prodigious market of religious ideas as they do about the pontiff's grumpy estimation of "modern civilization."

Meanwhile, there were what Burleigh calls "political religions." Eric Voegelin, in his 1938 book The Political Religions, used the term to describe the rise of totalitarian regimes in the twentieth century, but Burleigh thrusts the idea back into the prior century. It is an experience of religion that turns the system of symbols back on this world for their completion and satisfaction—what Voegelin called "world immanent" religion. Surveying the French Revolution, Tocqueville spoke of an "incomplete religion" possessed of saints, sacred calendars, festivals, and messianic ambitions which never transcend the merely chronological. The revolutionaries disembedded the old civic religion from its early medieval belief in Gallic exceptionalism, and threw its armies from Moscow to Cairo.

To understand the nineteenth century is to appreciate that these various senses of religion and faith were quite intermingled. Burleigh speaks reasonably enough of a "halfway stage in times when the symbolic world of Christianity was still known reality." Former seminarians and sons of preachers understood the symbols, and they knew how to provide simulacra of traditional and civic religion for the popular imagination. Civic catechisms, based on Lutheran and Tridentine models, were produced throughout Europe to extol nationalism. Garibaldi's catechism captured something of the Italian élan: "Thou shalt not fornicate, unless it be to harm the enemies of Italy." Other catechisms were more subtle or earnest, depending on the authors' estimation of the culture.

The point, however, is that political religion could never exist as a completely free-standing thing in nineteenth century Europe. It depended on symbolic world of Christianity. In three chapters on the Revolution and its aftermath in France, Burleigh examines one such effort to create and to impose a new religion as an alternative to Christianity. Revolutionaries created new calendars, pantheonized their heroes, invented festivals and liturgies of civic religion, culminating in the proclamation of the Cult of Reason in June 1794.

It was ultimately a flop. Within a few years time, Napoleon made his détente with the Church, and in 1815 the Bourbons were restored to the throne. But an important lesson was learned. The religion of the Revolution was unable to do two things which are the work of an earthly religion: to produce social solidarity and to constrain the passions. It was learned, then, that an alternative to the traditional religion had to look and feel a lot like the old one.

No less an authority than Edmund Burke spoke this sociological imperative. Religion is the basis of civil society, and both are "integral parts of the same whole." For neither the first nor the last time, it was the political Right that insisted religion must satisfy the two criteria of crowd-control and social solidarity. The Right soon had its chance to put its ideas into effect. At the Congress of Vienna, the great powers restored and otherwise propped up the alliances between throne and altar. Catholic, Protestant, and Orthodox leaders figured that, after the Enlightenment and the Revolution, religion was being granted a new lease on life. They were happy to pledge the obedience of the faithful in return. The pope urged Poles to submit to the tsar, who had plundered their churches, seminaries, and universities; the ecumenical patriarch similarly commanded the Greeks to obey the Ottomans.

Of course, by mid-century the throne-and-altar restoration had been swept away by revolutions and political turmoil. Indeed, it failed the twofold test of utility, neither guaranteeing crowd control nor social solidarity. Gradually, the utility argument passed into the hands of progressives, who understood that the Right had sets its sights too low. Rather than being a kind of police force in vestments, proper religion was a valuable resource for achieving the correct kind of order, now conceived as progress, and, above all, of nationalism.

The question remains, however: Why did nationalism become the way to harmonize religion and the state? A short and incomplete answer is that the state, with it apparatus of sovereignty, is a rather distant and cold object of loyalty. It was one thing to create state sovereignties, but quite another to make them habitable. States needed to win hearts and minds not merely by obedience, but a sense of belonging.

During the Revolution, the Committee for Public Safety decreed, "We will show this Fatherland to the citizen ceaselessly, in his laws, in his games, in his home, in his loves, in his festivities. We will never leave him to himself alone." The regime managed to infuriate almost everyone and to spark a popular uprising. Other states, notably England, learned to supply the warmth of a national culture much earlier. Italian unification not only emerged rather late but had to work hard to convince the people that it was not somewhat artificial. Gaining momentum throughout the century was the idea that the state is not an end in itself, but rather the exemplar, expression, and servant of national culture. Philosophers like Hegel and Fichte, poets like Heine, social scientists like Durkheim, and theologians from Schleirmacher to Troeltsch, argued that religion (properly understood) supplies the cultural warmth, the moral inspiration for what Bismarck would call "Practical Christianity."

No one could take very seriously the doctrine of a separation of church (much less religion) and the state. When that term was used—in France in 1905, for example—it did not mean what modern Americans might imagine. It meant, rather, de-clericalizing and a removal of ecclesiastical mediations of public things. In France, it meant specifically transferring church temporalities to cultural associations supervised by a minister of cults.

The spirit of the age was to meld together religion, culture, and state. The right-wing French nationalist, Charles Maurras, spoke of the gap to be healed between the juridical (pays légal) and the real nation (pays réel). Folklore abounded with charming notions of the sovereign awakening the sleeping beauty of the nation or, in the other direction, the nation presenting itself as the spotless bride to the sovereign. However the images were worked and reworked, the moral of story was that two forces split in modernity must go back together.

So powerful was the imperative of unity that Ernst Troeltsch could explain: "The great religious movement of modern times, the reawakened need for religions, develops outside the churches, and by and large outside theology as well." Lest there by doubt where he stood at the time of the Great War, he added, "The German faith is a faith in the inner moral and spiritual content of Germanness, the faith of the Germans in themselves, in their future, in their world mission." 

Earlier in the century, Fichte prophesied the need for a "fourth denomination," neither Lutheran, Reformed, or Catholic, but a Fatherland religion. Indeed, in 1822 Frederick William III merged Reformed and Lutheran into a Union. The Italian nationalist, Giuseppe Mazzini, declared: "We fell as a political party; we must rise again as a religious party. . . . Like sons of the same mother . . . the people shall gather around these two altars and offer sacrifice in peace and love."

Talk of divine providence was everywhere in the public domain—not the traditional notions of a general providence of created nature and the special providence of revelation proper. Rather, what could be called a third-track providence, which focused on a particular people specially covenanted and empowered. And if the first two providences were not outright denied, only the third-rail was entitled to interpret their truth. The Kaiser asserted: "On me, on me as the German Emperor, the Spirit of God has descended. I am His weapon, His sword and His visor." The comment raised eyebrows, but he was guilty of rhetorical excess rather than postulating a singular doctrine. All sides allowed themselves to speak of a holy war, a clash of civilizations directed by invisible powers—Odin against Bethlehem, as one English prelate put it—but interpreted and embodied by earthly ones.

Of course, none of this could have a happy ending. Religious authorities continually misunderstood the force of political religion. Many clergy and laity believed the religiously charged atmosphere of public policy was welcome evidence for the utility of religion in the modern world. To his credit, at the outset of the Great War, Karl Barth defied the political religion, going so far as to deny that Christianity is a religion at all. It was too late.

On this note, Burleigh rather abruptly ends Earthly Powers, with aftermath or summary, only the promise of a second volume on the totalitarian era. Given the complicated history Burleigh sets out to explain, no title will exactly capture the material. Even so, his readers might complain that the subtitle—The Clash of Religion and Politics—is misleading. There wasn't much of a clash, and that indeed is the scandal of the story.

What conflicts there were tended to erupt within the precincts of Catholicism. One reason is that Rome was never happy with the process of state-formation. In 1648, Innocent X, declared the treaties of Westphalia "null, void, invalid, iniquitous, unjust, damnable, reprobate, inane, empty of meaning and effect for all time." The new system of sovereign states caused the slow decline of the twin international colossi of papacy and Holy Roman Empire. But what choice was there except to adapt to what were de facto national churches? The Vatican was dependent on Catholic sovereigns to politically and militarily hold the line in the Counter-Reformation and to supply the material infrastructure for the ever-growing missions in the Americas and Asia. For their part, Catholic sovereigns understood that they needn't do anything so radical as Henry VIII's schism to enjoy a functional supremacy in matters religious. 

At mid-nineteenth century, there was no consensus in the Catholic world about whether a proper understanding of theology should lead in prudence, if not in principle, to less or more political liberty. There was, however, an emerging consensus on one point: The Church had to extricate itself from state control and to return to what John Courtney Murray would later call the "Gregorian state of the question."

He was referring to Gregory VII. The proposition that the liberty of the Church was the precondition for tackling the issue of how Catholicism is to be incarnated in states and nations began on political Right. In the early days of the Restoration, the doyen of Catholic conservatives, Joseph de Maistre, insisted that Gregory VII's work be completed in modern times. He remorselessly criticized the ecclesiology of national churches, taunting Gallicans to change the creed to read, "I believe in divided and in dependent Churches." He insisted that "nothing is accomplished" without overthrowing the "magic castle" of regalism, and accused kings and princes of a "great rebellion." A succession of Catholic writers picked up the theme. Félicité de Lamennais, Dom Guéranger, Henri Lacordaire, John Henry Newman, Bishop Wilhelm Emmanuel von Ketteler, Antonio Rosmini, among others, wrote tracts on the Gregorian reform and its application to the present crisis.

None of this was initially well received in Rome. Joseph de Maistre felt slighted by Pius VII who didn't respond enthusiastically to an autographed copy of Du Pape, which had made the papacy out to be the very center of the périmètre sacre, the sacred boundary. Four decades later, Antonio Rosmini, a papalist, but moderately liberal in political matters, received even shabbier treatment for arguing that state nomination of bishops was one of Christ's five wounds. Only Guéranger managed to beat this drum while keeping intact his credentials in Rome. He was one of the only players in the story who grasped how the Gregorian theme would lead to the First Vatican Council. 

In any event, this kind of talk did not appear to popes as conservative but radical, which indeed it was. Three popes of the Restoration era heard the message and dismissed it. Replaying Canossa meant the loss the papal states, which depended on the military and political support of Catholic sovereigns.

And then Pius IX lost his temporal dominions in 1860. In the years leading up to this loss, Pius had issued numerous acerbic claims and complaints about the liberty of the Church. No one paid much attention until they showed up in the Syllabus of Errors (1864). The eighty condemned propositions were culled from encyclicals and occasional decrees, and then roughly grouped according to major themes. The European press had considerable sport with the last proposition, "The Roman Pontiff can, and ought, reconcile himself, and come to terms with progress, liberalism and modern civilization." Catholic spin-meisters worked overtime to put the best construction on it. Bishop Dupanloup of Orléans wrote the most famous defense: "Where do we find it written," he demanded, "'Outside the Code Napoléon there is no salvation'?"

Underneath the journalistic mockery of the Syllabus, cabinets and courts in European capitals suspected that Duplanloup had the right interpretation. They viewed with alarm sections 19 to 55 of the Syllabus, which taken together suggested that Pius would pull the plug on familiar church-state relations. Temporal sovereigns would no longer enjoy an inherent right to co-govern the Church. Their suspicion was confirmed in 1868 when Rome issued a bull of indiction for a Vatican Council but left out the customary invitation to the temporal sovereigns to send ambassadors, the oratores. Even more alarming was a rumor that a Vatican committee had drafted a document entitled De Ecclesia Christi, which included several chapters and canons on Church and state.

In France, Émile Ollivier declared in the Chamber of Deputies that the pope had in effect introduced the separation of church and state: "Yes, this is a new fact, a new deed indeed that the disseverance between the laical society and the religious society is put into effect by the pope's own hand." He went on to say, "Undoubtedly, Gentlemen, I know that Rome earnestly wishes to separate itself from the State, but She does not want the State to separate itself from Her." Neatly, Ollivier managed to summarize what the nineteenth-century Catholic imagination attributed to Gregory VII: one-way separation. It was the mirror-image of what state nationalisms had claimed for themselves. In France, Germany, and England there was some talk about military intervention to stop this mutinous act in its tracks. But the ever-prudent English decided to let events take their own turn.

As it turned out, the bishops at the council could reach no consensus. No over-arching theory could overcome all of the practical concerns and consequences. Most of the attenders were under pressure by the home governments to stay clear of these propositions. So, they reached a conclusion without a theoretical apparatus and awarded the papacy the principle of universal jurisdiction, indirectly settling the matter. There would be no national churches, no inherent right of temporal sovereigns to nominate or veto the episcopal office. The Austrian government, the remnant of the old Roman Empire in the West, promptly annulled her concordat with the Church.

The point to be drawn is that, in the summer of 1870, Rome had, at best, only very tense relationships with the former Catholic nations. When the British envoy asked Pius' secretary of state, Cardinal Antonelli, why the Vatican failed to invite ambassadors from Catholic nations to the Council, the secretary said that "exclusively Catholic Governments had virtually ceased to exist."

This was an exaggeration, but one that was more true than false. Surveying the political landscape there was no model for how the Catholic religion could be properly aligned with the twin forces of state sovereignty and nationalism. At least nothing comparable to Anglicanism in England, or Protestantism in Prussia, or Orthodoxy in Russia. For several decades, Catholic liberals urged the adoption of the Belgian model, for its 1831 constitution was the first of its kind to abandon traditional powers to nominate bishops or veto ecclesiastical business. Burleigh mistakenly refers to the Belgian constitution as a "separation" of church and state, though Belgium, without the props of a concordat, supplied clerical salaries and religious education with state subsidies. Unfortunately, the Belgian experiment happened in the thick of the Restoration era. By 1870, when it would have looked like a very good model indeed, Belgium had drifted into prickly clerical-versus-anti-clerical politics.

The political poverty of the Church can be measured by the fact that Rome had a deep and abiding mistrust of party politics, especially parties with the Catholic label. The fifteen-hundred year habit of dealing with Catholic sovereigns was not easily translated into non-kingly politics. The Centre Party in Germany was usually on the outs with the Vatican. In Italy, the popes imposed the non-expedit, forbidding Catholics from participating in the new regime. It was lifted only 1919, on the condition that the new Popular Italian Party remain nondenominational. While the Church taught clearly enough about powers higher than the state, its approach to things lower than the state tended to emphasize, very conservatively, guilds and associations more like sodalities than political parties. In this way, Catholic activism from below could be kept within the orbit of ecclesiastical authority and Church unity preserved.

Out of its strengths and weaknesses, European Catholicism was at least partially immunized against the temptation of giving itself corporately over to the new political religion of nationalism. Burleigh writes: "Since Roman Catholics were primarily attached to the universal Church, they had difficulties in regarding the nation as the highest form of human community that God had established, something which they had in common with the Enlightenment belief in human universality, however much they may have despised and feared other aspects of that variegated project."

The proofs of Burleigh's interesting generalization are the Leonine encyclicals, beginning with Aeterni Patris. Leo had little use for the current species of Romanticism, especially as resourced by the political right, which, in France, was quite capable of conjoining religion and historical nostalgia to a blood-and-ethnicity politic. Indeed, Leo's sorest problem came from the intransigent Right. Leo's program was shaped by his worry that Catholicism had not responded adequately to the Enlightenment. This explains why his encyclicals return over and over again to the problem of the relation between faith and reason, the differentiation of the sciences, the role of natural law, the basis and scope of natural right of property, the question of whether there are pre-political states of nature, and whether Deism is an adequate natural theology.

In France, monarchist and traditionalist Catholics were appalled that Leo had gone so far as to insist that, by nature, there are plural legitimate forms of polity. In a letter addressed to all French Catholics, he wrote that while the Church must cross the "changeable ocean of human affairs," it has no legitimate prudence over its "essential constitution," received directly from Christ; but, "in regard to purely human societies, it is an oft-repeated historical fact that time, that great transformer of all things here below, operates great changes in their political institutions."

For Leo the two expressions of providence—natural law and the apodictic divine revelation—set boundaries, but did not cancel out prudence. Prudence, functioning within the bounds of absolute norms, made unnecessary any appeal to a providence that made human history absolute. In an 1892 allocution, Leo XIII told his cardinals that the church's temporal mission would center on "faith embodied in the conscience of peoples rather than restoration of medieval institutions." His magisterial letters focused on a formation of conscience and prudence, and how to distinguish the two from the heterodox notions of historical destiny.

The most important, long lasting, and interesting Catholic movement after 1789 to take up the question of providence and prudence was the Cult of the Sacred Heart, with its companion cults arising from Marian apparitions. The Cult of the Sacred Heart was politically charged from the beginning, and it would assume different political and spiritual complexions as Catholicism was stripped of its political authority. Still, while the popes and the laity did not always see things eye-to-eye on the utility of political parties, they were joined in their appreciation of the Sacred Heart. The cult had medieval antecedents, but it is the modern one that is of interest to us. Burleigh mentions it, but it deserves something more than a passing note. For the cult ambiguously contained the material for a potent Catholic nationalisms as well as for a state and nation transcending universalism. A twenty-six year old Visitationist nun in the convent of Paray-le-Monial, Marguerite-Marie Alacoque, began receiving apparitions of the Sacred Heart in 1673. From February to August of 1689 Marguerite-Marie passed to her superior, first, a message to Catholic kings, and then a special message to the Sun King, Louis XIV. If only Louis would put the image of the Heart on his military standards, and consecrate his government to the Passion of Christ, he would become a Constantine. Eventually, the Heart become a political and military symbol not only of French exceptionalism, but well into the nineteenth century of Catholic political restoration.

In Annum Sacrum, Leo made clear that, as the Church entered the twentieth century, it should no longer place its temporal hopes in the arrangements of the old political order. Once, he said, divine providence raised up a Constantine to deliver the Church from "the yoke of the Caesars." Today, however, "another blessed and heavenly token is offered to our sight—the most Sacred Heart of Jesus, with a cross rising from it and shining forth with dazzling splendor amidst flames of love. In that Sacred Heart all our hopes should be placed, and from it the salvation of men is to be confidently besought." Leo understood that the Heart had to be affirmed without the political doctrines of nationalism and exceptionalism. He called the dedication "the greatest act of my pontificate."

To complete the international direction of Leo's Annum Sacrum, Pius published Quas primas in 1925, declaring the Feast of Christ the King. It was written, among other reasons, to tame the Maurrasian nationalist movement with its debased, secularized version of special national covenants. A few months after the encyclical was published, Pius XI addressed 191 descendants of Catholic martyrs from the French Revolution, who were urged to reject "integral nationalism" in favor of "integral obedience" to Christ. Indeed, in the late 1920s it became a custom to contextualize the Heart in light of Christ the King.

Today, it will seem a strange thing to make Jesus's heart visually subordinate to Christ's kingship, but once on a time it was a profound exercise of political theology. It was nothing less than the way to preserve the Catholic imagination from what I have called the third-rail providences of nationalisms and political religions. The human and earthly Jesus of the Heart is also the fully transcendent King.

Burleigh skates the surface of this history in Earthly Powers. His most thought provoking insight is that the argument for the utility of religion typically begins on the Right as an effort to preserve the role of religion in buttressing social order, but moves inexorably to the Progressives, with their visions of providential exceptionalism and nationalism. Yet he does not elaborate the pattern in a way that allows us to draw a lesson. He leaves out, for instance, the American amalgamation of political and civic religions, with its peculiar version of third-rail providence. By the late nineteenth century, the American version was so important that it requires an historian of Europe to give at least a sidelong glance at what Lincoln meant by the "almost chosen" people, and to the subsequent volatility of the "almost." Finally, Burleigh raises, without adequate reflection, a most interesting prospect. In western modernity, atheism never quite bottoms out. A religion, or more likely, an ersatz or political religion, always emerges to cushion its fall and to redirect its energies. Is this a good thing? Is it the role of religion to keep atheism from bottoming out? Earthly Powers never quite reckons with the questions which transcend the story.

Russell Hittinger is Warren Professor of Catholic Studies and Research Professor of Law at the University of Tulsa



iPadから送信

Sunday, June 10, 2018

Does Buddhist detachment allow for a healthier togetherness? | Aeon Essays

Does Buddhist detachment allow for a healthier togetherness? | Aeon Essays

Buddhists in love

Lovers crave intensity, Buddhists say craving causes suffering. Is it possible to be deeply in love yet truly detached?

Humans are social animals. We live in groups. We care for our offspring for years. We cooperate with each other (the United States Congress notwithstanding). Most of all, we have lasting relationships with other individual humans – what biologists call long-term pair bonds.

Some of these pair bonds, you've surely noticed, are healthier than others. That's where the field of relationship science comes in. Relationship scientists study how to build and maintain strong, intimate relationships. We perform laboratory experiments to understand the factors that make a relationship flourish or wither.

In recent years, some researchers in relationship science, including us, have turned to a surprising resource for inspiration: Buddhism. We say 'surprising' because one of the central tenets of Buddhism is letting go of strong attachments, but a relationship is the very definition of a strong attachment. How can these opposing ideas be reconciled? And what does science have to say?

Let's begin with some basics about biology. In a healthy relationship, you feel good when your partner is around. No surprise there. But you might not know that the good feeling happens because you and your partner regulate each other's nervous systems.

The process starts with your brain. Contrary to popular belief, your brain's most important job isn't thinking. It's maintaining all the biological systems in your body so your organs, hormones and immune system run efficiently and remain in balance. Your brain does this by predicting and fulfilling your bodily needs 24/7. If you need to stand up, for example, your brain predicts and executes a (hopefully) appropriate change in blood pressure so you don't faint. If your brain predicts you're going to be low on salt, you will crave salty foods. And so on.

This ongoing process is like running a budget for your body. Think about your financial budget, where you keep track of your income and spending to try to stay solvent. Your brain does the same thing, but instead of money, it budgets resources such as water, salt and glucose. If a financial budget goes into the red (say, when you take out a loan to buy a car), you have to pay back what you borrowed and, if all goes well, then over time your budget stays mostly in balance. The same is true for your body budget: you can run a race to exhaustion but then must replenish or 'pay back' your resources by resting, eating and drinking. The scientific name for this balancing act is allostasis. The brain's goal is to maintain a balanced body budget most of the time and to pay back any debts that arise. This process must be quick and efficient, because budget-balancing is itself a costly endeavour for the brain.

Now here's the cool part. Humans help to balance each other's body budgets. When a baby is born, the adults in her life regulate her body budget by feeding her, cuddling her and talking to her. They teach her when to fall asleep at the right time. They play games with her and read to her. These activities provide the body-budgeting she needs for her brain to develop normally. This is the biological basis of attachment between a child and her caregivers. Eventually, the child becomes able to regulate her own nervous system and balance her own body budget, but the communal body-budgeting never completely stops.

Attachment between adults works similarly. Most of us can clothe and feed ourselves and know when to put on a sweater to regulate our temperature, but we must also deal with the demands of a job, lack of sleep and no time to exercise, eating too many pseudo-foods, maybe living or working in noisy or crowded conditions, and battling the idiots who block our way now and then. Managing a body budget in this world is a monumental task. So, we need other people around us to help keep our budget solvent and stay healthy.

What's the cost of not having healthy attachments to other people? Scientists who study loneliness have provided a clear answer: a 30 per cent higher risk of death when those reporting isolation at the time of the initial interview were followed up seven years later. That's higher than the risk of dying from a well-known disease such as obesity. A single, lonely brain spends so many resources trying to keep in balance that it starts running a long-term deficit. The brain then treats the body like it's sick. If this process goes on for long enough, the immune system gets involved and the result could be earlier-onset diabetes, heart disease, depression, cancer or other illnesses related to metabolism.

Healthy relationships help you to live longer. You and your partner unconsciously regulate each other's nervous systems to your mutual benefit. Your heart rates synchronise. So does your breathing. Even your hormones align. In moments of stress, a hug, a light caress or a kind word from your partner helps to ease your body-budget burden. Sharing this burden is the biological basis of attachment.

Subscribe to our newsletter

Updates on everything new at Aeon.

The best thing for your nervous system is another person. Unfortunately, the worst thing for your nervous system is also another person. An unhealthy relationship can screw up your body budget and, with it, your health and your life. So what makes for a healthy or unhealthy relationship, and how do you maintain one? Buddhism offers a set of guidelines for how to treat your partner (and yourself) to minimise suffering. The logic here is not straightforward and requires some explanation, so here's a short primer on Buddhism.

Buddhism has been around for thousands of years. Some think of it as a religion, others as a set of principles for living a good life. Either way, millions of people in the Western world have realised that you needn't be a Buddhist to understand and try some of its ideas. Numerous books explain how to apply Buddhism to be happier, healthier and more mindful. But Buddhism is more than just a reason to buy a meditation cushion. It holds some ironic secrets to a more satisfying, quality relationship.

A key idea of Buddhism is that everything constantly changes. Any object, such as a red tulip in your garden, changes moment to moment. Its colours change depending on the light. The sheen on its petals changes depending on moisture in the air. Placed in the wrong location, such as a vegetable garden, a tulip ceases to be a flower and becomes a weed. The tulip has no single, unchanging essence. The same is true for you. You are real – you exist – but, from a Buddhist perspective, you have no intrinsic identity that is separate from the things going on around you. Your identity is constituted in the moment, in part, by your situation.

If you believe that you have a single, consistent, unchanging, core 'self' that uniquely defines you, this belief, according to Buddhist philosophy, is the foundation of human suffering. Here, suffering is not merely physical discomfort, like having the flu or shutting a door on your hand. Suffering is personal: you'll toil to avoid feeling flawed in some way. You'll constantly worry about your reputation or that you're failing to live up to standards created by others. In this sense, believing that you have one true self is worse than a passing physical illness; it is an enduring affliction (translation: a chronically imbalanced body budget).

Many people go through life believing that they have an unchanging, core identity. They usually also think that their friends, families, acquaintances and lovers have enduring selves as well. No wonder, because we describe ourselves in this way all the time. We go on dates and quiz each other about what we're like. In job interviews, the classic question is: 'Tell me about yourself.' Zillions of surveys you see online and in magazines ask you to describe yourself: are you an introvert or an extrovert? A dog person or cat person? When we answer these kinds of questions, we are almost always looking to reveal the unchanging features of a core, enduring identity.

Appreciate the tulip because it's there, not because you're there

Buddhism warns that the enduring self is an illusion. Instead, your 'self' depends on context. It's normal to be friendly in one situation, shy in another, and rude in a third. When you cling to the fiction that you have a real, enduring and important self – known as reifying the self – this sets you up for a miserable life. You will crave material things that bolster this fiction. You'll crave wealth. You'll crave power. You'll cling to compliments and adoration from others, even if they're lies. But the real problem here is not that others deceive you, but that you are deceiving yourself. These cravings are golden handcuffs that bring immediate pleasure but also, by reinforcing your illusory self, entrap you and cause persistent suffering, negative emotion, and enslavement to a fragile and fictional existence.

One of Buddhism's main tools to avoid reifying the self (or objects in the world) is mindfulness meditation. According to certain styles of Buddhist philosophy, all human experiences can be broken down into basic elements, kind of like 'atoms' that make up thoughts, feelings and perceptions. Wisdom, in Buddhist terms, means experiencing these basic elements directly, without the haze of cravings and desires that come along with the belief in an unchanging self. Mindfulness meditation can break through the illusion that objects and other people and even you are the same from moment to moment. Then we can see things as they truly are, experiencing each moment as raw sensation without implication beyond the moment itself.

For example, if you encounter an invasive tulip in your vegetable garden, you might be tempted to rip it out of the ground, or pick it to give to your lover. A Buddhist perspective would be that you're seeing the tulip through a filter of your own needs and desires, which are bound up with your illusory idea of self. To see the tulip as it truly is, you must let go of self-focused stories about the tulip – how it doesn't belong there, or how much your lover would like it – and experience the tulip in a way that's unrelated to your own needs. Notice its beautiful colour. Be awed by the power of nature. Experience the irony of a flower thriving among the legumes. Appreciate the tulip because it's there, not because you're there. In Buddhist philosophy, this is a key facet of wisdom.

What does this wisdom mean in practice? You can use it to access your own experience more clearly. When you feel furious and have a pounding heartbeat and a sweaty brow, it is easy to get caught up in a story about that fury and even fuel more of it. But meditation can help you attend to the heartbeat and the sweating as purely physical sensations, and let the anger dissolve. In Buddhist terminology, you're deconstructing your anger – and your illusory self – into its basic elements and gaining wisdom in the process. Deconstructing the self isn't easy: it can take years to become skilled at it (just ask a Buddhist monk), but it's possible with practice.

Another practical application of this wisdom is the simple recognition of change. A close look at the tulip reveals constant change, and that's true of you too. So, for example, you could be scrupulously honest one day and a cheating skunk the next, and neither one represents your true self because you don't have one. You are simply configured differently in the two situations. This kind of outlook can cultivate compassion for yourself when you behave badly or screw up. You're not intrinsically a bad person – you just behaved badly in some context.

The idea of a constantly changing self is echoed in modern psychology. Sometimes you represent yourself by your career. Sometimes you're a friend. Sometimes you're a parent, or a child, or a lover. Sometimes you're a musician, an artist, a cook, a handyman. Sometimes you're just a body. Social psychologists model this diversity as 'multiple selves', based on pioneering research in the 1980s by the social psychologist Hazel Markus, who showed that people have a repertoire of different selves for different occasions.

All of these ideas apply not only to your own self, but also to the selves of others. When you reify someone else, you mistake the person who is with you in the present moment as enduring in time, with no change. Thus, that 'psycho ex' whom you dated last year is both a 'psycho' and an 'ex' today and forever. This mindset is seen as a barrier to compassion that enhances suffering in the world. Instead, Buddhism suggests that you try to see other people as they actually are, even your nutty ex. When you don't reify them in terms of your own needs – think of the tulip here – you can more easily have compassion for them. In the process, you reduce their suffering and yours.

At first glance, Buddhism seems at odds with the scientific evidence that people are social animals. We know that strong attachments to other people are vital for your health; without them, you wither and die sooner. Buddhism, on the other hand, suggests that relationships involving strong attachments can be problematic, precisely because those attachments make it difficult to see ourselves and others clearly. But ironically, Buddhist thought also offers some compelling suggestions for building and maintaining healthy bonds that are echoed in the emerging science of relationships.

The first suggestion is don't reify your partner. Have you ever heard a friend complain about his partner (or ex), saying: 'He isn't the man I thought he was,' or 'She's a different person now'? In Buddhist terms, your friend is suffering because he reified his partner in the service of reifying himself. It's a common story. Two people meet, they get to know each other, and they experience strong feelings for each other based on that knowledge. In neuroscience terms, strong feelings for another person are always accompanied by the brain's beliefs of what the other person is like. Those beliefs, which neuroscientists call predictions, are like a filter through which you learn about and experience the other person in terms of your own needs. Such filters set you up to reify your fictional self and your partner.

Buddhist philosophy offers another route. Passion, desire and intensity of feeling aren't necessarily bad if you harness them to understand who the other person is – not an unchanging self, but an individual in a given situation. Go ahead and have strong feelings, but drop the story about your partner (that is, resist the predictions) accompanying those feelings. Instead, treat the feelings as a signal to learn who your partner is right now, in the moment. Be open to learning something new (or as neuroscientists put it, learning 'prediction error').

Relationship science suggests that romantic relationships are healthier when you and your partner see each other in an unrealistically positive light. This phenomenon, called positive illusions, involves exaggerating or even imagining positive qualities in your partner. Oddly enough, there's evidence that positive illusions can bolster healthy relationships. Couples who idealise one another feel more satisfied in their relationship. From a Buddhist perspective, however, these types of illusions usually emerge from the need to cling to your reified sense of self. In the long run, they can lead to unrealistic expectations and disappointment. Instead, try accentuating the positive without the illusions. People are more satisfied with their marriages when their spouses see virtues in them that they do not see themselves. An easy way to do this is to see your partner's actions in the most charitable light.

For example, suppose your spouse is inattentive to details, and shoves items into the refrigerator without considering what might get knocked over. You could frame this behaviour as stupidity, or in terms of the inconvenience it causes you, or even as a positive illusion ('He's an absent-minded genius'). Or instead, you could frame this behaviour in a more charitable light: that your spouse has a lot on his or her mind, or is getting older. You could even view your spouse's inattentiveness as a positive quality, like not noticing that new roll of pudge around your middle.

When you view your partner's actions in a charitable light, you're not creating a fiction, you're acknowledging the many possibilities for what your partner's actions mean. Like the tulip, your partner is ever-changing.

If you decline to fight, the conflict fizzles and provides an opportunity to flourish

But what if you and your partner's problems are more serious than a battle over fridge space? What if your partner utters snide remarks intended to cause you pain, or even takes a swing at your head? First and foremost, you have to make sure that you're physically safe. A Buddhist perspective would never be to stand there being mindful. But afterward, Buddhism offers a perspective on what to do next. Partners who let loose with abusive behaviour are trying to achieve some goal, often to make themselves feel better, bolster self-esteem and reify the self. They're confused about how to relieve their own suffering. If you understand the root of their aggression, it is easier to foster compassion and empathy for them. Compassion doesn't mean that you agree to be a punching bag. But it gives you space to consider ways to prevent others from harming you further, and from harming themselves.

A great example happened in December 2017 when the actress Sarah Silverman was trolled on Twitter by Jeremy Jamrozy, who called her a 'cunt'. Instead of firing back or ignoring the Tweet, Silverman responded with compassion. She read Jamrozy's Twitter profile and guessed that he was being abusive because he was in severe pain. She started a conversation with him, he apologised, and Silverman helped him look for a back specialist. The story went viral, and Jamrozy established a crowdfunding campaign for his $150 in medical expenses. The campaign raised more than $4,500 – all because Silverman took time to understand the feelings behind the insult. A battle requires two opponents, so if you decline to fight, then the conflict fizzles and provides an opportunity to flourish.

Of course, compassion sometimes isn't enough to help others out of the maze of their own confusion. Wisdom also means knowing when to quit the relationship. A Buddhist approach is to separate without being angry and vindictive. Anger is a form of ignorance of the other person's perspective. If you cannot dissolve that anger with an injection of mindfulness, then at the very least, try to shower a little compassion on yourself.

The second Buddhism-inspired suggestion for a healthy relationship is don't see your partner only in terms of yourself. You probably know some people who think everything revolves around them. They do things for others because it gets them what they want. For example, if you received an offer of a new job, your partner might push you to negotiate a higher salary not for your own happiness, but because you are your partner's meal ticket. You're treated like an object as your partner reifies his or her self. In a healthier relationship, your partner would see you as a person with your own thoughts, feelings, experiences and needs that are important to you. It's OK to earn less if it's a more fulfilling job. This mindset, which relationship scientists call responsiveness, shows compassion for you, and ultimately reduces suffering for you and your partner.

The third suggestion derived from Buddhist ideas is that relationships are constructed by two people in synchrony. A Buddhist concept called mutuality (or shared karma) means that two people can have shared intentions and actions that lead to shared consequences. In relationship science, mutuality is called goal interdependence.

Mutuality is beneficial for romantic relationships. For example, suppose your partner comes up behind you and rubs your shoulders. Maybe the gesture means he or she is grateful to be with you or simply wants to be close to you. Or maybe it's a request for sex. Either way, as long as you and your partner agree on the meaning – gratitude, closeness, lust – you are constructing your relationship together. In neuroscience terms, mutuality means that the predictions launched by your brain and your partner's brain in the moment are compatible.

Mutuality is about creating a story together, as more than mere actors in each other's narratives

Being in agreement is not enough, however, if your partner is also reifying you: feeling possessive rather than grateful, or objectifying you rather than connecting with you. These meanings have nothing to do with you per se, and everything to do with your partner's cravings. Even if you're in agreement, your relationship is in trouble. Mutuality is about creating a story together, sharing experiences where you're more than mere actors in each other's narratives.

Together with our colleagues Christy Wilson-Mendenhall at the University of Wisconsin-Madison and Paul Condon at Southern Oregon University, we study couples to explore the connections between Buddhism, bonding and body budgets. When a couple interacts, how often do they cherish each other in the moment? When they successfully cherish each another, does it lead to more kindness, compassion and a healthier relationship? And do they balance each other's body budgets in the process?

Until our studies are complete, Buddhism remains an intriguing source of inspiration for building and maintaining meaningful relationships. As Markus writes: 'You can't be a self by yourself.'

This Essay was made possible through the support of a grant from Templeton Religion Trust to Aeon. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of Templeton Religion Trust.

Funders to Aeon Magazine are not involved in editorial decision-making, including commissioning or content approval.

Syndicate this Essay



iPadから送信

Saturday, June 09, 2018

Even if you build it, the poor can’t come: against supply-side | Aeon Ideas

Even if you build it, the poor can't come: against supply-side | Aeon Ideas

Even if you build it, the poor can't come: against supply-side

No fly zone: The main terminal at Ciudad Real Airport in Spain. Completed in 2009 at a cost of 1.1 billion euros, the airport is now unused. <em>Photo by Oli Scarff/Getty</em>

'If you build it, they will come.' It's a Latin saying – Si tu id aeficas, ei venient – but it's probably more recognisable because it sounds like what that disembodied voice says to Kevin Costner in the film Field of Dreams (1989). And in the film, Costner does build it (a baseball field) and people do come. In either case, it's a good way of summing up the case for supply-side economics. 

But to understand that case, we need to break it down into its constituent elements. And the thinking behind it goes like this: if you want to stimulate the economy, then cut taxes on the rich (those who invest in and build things) and they will use this extra money to produce more stuff. Why? Because supply creates its own demand, so if they produce more they will sell more, and the economy will expand. An expanding economy, in turn, benefits everybody. There will be more jobs, wages will be higher, and government budget deficits will shrink. This latter effect, of course, might seem counterintuitive. But the argument is that even though tax rates go down, the amount of economic activity these cuts unleash will grow everyone's income to such an extent that the total tax collected by the government, even at these lower rates, will actually go up. That's what the supply-siders contend.

Given that the supply-side approach has been the policy of the Republican Party for decades, this argument has proved convincing to a lot of people. But let's look at it a little more carefully. The notion that supply creates its own demand is known as Say's law, after the French economist Jean-Baptiste Say (1767-1832) who is credited with its formulation. The thought is that when you produce more, you have to spend additional money to do so. This additional spending, in turn, provides people with extra income, and therefore the wherewithal to buy the additional goods you have created.

Of course, you cannot just build anything. To sell more of something, it has to be something that people actually want. Say himself acknowledged this. But let's focus on the mechanics of how increasing production is supposed to give people the wherewithal to purchase more of what they do want. Unfortunately, the presumptions here just don't make sense.

First, at most, building more goods simply introduces funds equivalent to their cost of production into the economy. But things don't sell for their cost of production­ – no one builds anything unless they think they can price it at a profit. And if you don't think people will have enough new money to pay this price, why would you increase production?

Second, a lot of the costs of production are what economists call 'fixed' costs; that is, the cost of big things such as factories and office buildings and expensive machines and equipment, rather than the costs of the additional labour and supplies necessary to build one extra thing, which are called 'marginal' costs. The total cost of production combines fixed and marginal costs, and fixed costs usually represent the far greater share. This means that when you build more stuff, it is not true that all the costs of production are introduced into the economy as new money. You have merely injected new money to the extent you have incurred additional marginal costs. And it is unlikely that a producer would take the risk of ramping up production in a troubled economic environment if all that could be recovered was the marginal costs.

Third, producers receive many of the goods needed in the production of further goods from their suppliers on credit. Why presume that all the marginal costs of additional production have actually been paid at the time the goods hit the shelves? Or that the ultimate consumer is going to be willing to use credit to increase consumption in troubled times, even if those higher up the chain have used credit to increase production? More concerning still, if consumers do use credit, unless we later provide them with more income, we will have simply set ourselves up for another financial collapse when the teaser rates on their loans time out and further payments become unaffordable, as happened in 2008.

Subscribe to our newsletter

Updates on everything new at Aeon.

None of these problems with supply-side thinking will come as a surprise to anyone who runs a business. They are happy to see their taxes cut, sure, but they are not going to use this extra money to increase production unless they think that their customers will have enough new money to buy these additional goods. And no reasonable business person thinks that enough new money can be introduced by increasing production alone. If they did, record amounts of cash wouldn't be sitting in corporate bank accounts doing nothing, which is what has been happening for years now. Obviously, the people who control this cash don't believe that supply creates its own demand. They think that increasing production without first seeing an increase in demand would be foolhardy.

History is also not on the supply-siders' side. To see the failure of the supply-side approach at the national level, all we need do is look at the 2001 and 2003 tax cuts signed into law by the then president of the United States, George W Bush. These tax cuts did not increase investment or production. Rather, the rich either hoarded this additional money or used it to bid up the price of existing assets, creating asset bubbles and exponentially increasingly economic inequality. And because economic activity did not increase enough to offset the loss of government revenue from reduced taxes, the deficit exploded. To see a similar result on the state level, in turn, we can look at the recent supply-side 'Kansas experiment'. There, massive tax cuts on the rich and corporations almost bankrupted the state.

Remember also that in the 19th century, when Say devised his law, there was a huge amount of untapped demand for new goods; most costs were marginal costs; and most transactions were for cash, not credit. At that time, perhaps it seemed like supply did create its own demand. But not today. Today, to stimulate the economy, we need to increase demand first. And the best way to do this is by putting more money in the hands of the people whom the economist John Maynard Keynes described in 1936 as having the highest 'marginal propensity to consume'. These are not the rich, but rather the poor and middle-class. For, as a group, these are the people who can be counted on to spend all their income whereas, as we have already seen, the rich are likely to keep a chunk of it in cash. Once demand is increased among the poor and middle-class, Keynes argued, production will rise to meet it.

In deciding whether to go with the supply-side or the Keynesian approach to stimulating the economy, there is one more consideration that is relevant. Recent history has shown that we can't be sure that economic expansion alone will solve our wider economic problems. Almost all of the benefits of economic growth during the past 30 years or so have accrued to the rich, and mostly to the super-rich. Real income for most people has been stagnant or even declined. The new jobs that have been created are mostly temporary, low-wage, no-benefit jobs. Permanent, good-wage jobs with benefits have continued to disappear. Rather than giving money to the rich in these circumstances and hoping that it trickles down to the rest of us, as the supply-siders suggest, it would be better to give money to the poor and middle-class, as the Keynesians suggest. The Keynesian approach, after all, has worked many times in the past. Indeed, it's how the West emerged from the Great Depression. But most importantly, if for some reason it doesn't work, at least we will have made the right people better off.



iPadから送信

Monday, June 04, 2018

Sacra doctrina

http://www.sacradoctrina.it/domenicanimilano/s2magazine/css/0/sacra/images/files/ANDREA%20BONAZZI%20Sacra%20Doctrina%202015.01-02.pdf

Balthasar su collegamento tra buddismo e marxismo in Cina

"(...)uno sguardo schietto sulla concreta storia del mondo indica due cose: anzitutto quanto poco ovvia e' stata e ancora e' per la massima parte dell'umanita' extrabiblica la conclusione dalla soggettivita' dell'io finito alla soggettivita' dell'assoluto (si pensi qui anche solo alla massima parte della religiosita' asiatica), e in secondo luogo con quanta forza le ideologie postcristiane (in parte certo in collegamento con la situazione appena menzionata: Cina) possono respingere una simile conclusione come un vero e proprio tradimento alla liberta' umana. Queste due cose devono renderci assai cauti a sottolineare la capacita' effettiva di un 'esistenziale sovrannaturale'".
(H. U. von Balthasar, Teodrammatica, vol. 4, pp. 128-129)

K 神父へ 

私の感想 (ご参考にならないかもしれない)

大変ひろくて深みのある議論、博学多識な論じ方で、すべてをチェックするのはかなり時間がかかります。また、プロテスタントとしてはめずらしく、聖書ばっかりではなく、哲学もさまざまな学問をも扱っていて、とても勉強になります。著作全体として、ヘーゲルの弁証法の色が勝っている印象を受けます。私は若い時にヘーゲルの魅力をたっぷり感じましたので、懐かしく思うところはたくさんあります。ソ連崩壊まえのヨーロッパの雰囲気を感じます。
もちろん、パネンベルクはヘーゲル哲学を、オーソドックスな神学に使えるために、見直したつもりでしょうけれども、これで満足いくかというと、疑問はのこります。
たとえば、「人格」という概念から考えてみる、そして東洋思想における人格という観点から考えてみる。東洋における人格の概念の背後には、人間は感情と感性の収束であるとする考えが常に存在している。これは確かに心理的自意識の分野に統括されるのであるが、同時にそれは、現象界一般と同じく、人格を幻影(あるいはsunyata [空])の世界に属するものでもあるのである。また、それは例えば「輪廻転生」という考えになっていく。つまり、別の肉体の中に同じ本質を有する霊魂が転生するか、それとも「前生」の残存としてのカルマをめぐる新たな心理的な感覚の核が形成されるか。したがってそれは、同一性というよりは「前生」から引きずる継続性の主張である。要するに東洋では存在論的人格の基点を想定せず、心理的人格の核心すらも、単なる幻想であり、「無我」あるいは「マーヤ(幻)」であるとする。
また、超越性の問題は必ずしもこれに続いて登場するわけではなく、例えば「梵我一如」というようなかたちでおかれる。
パネンベルクは東洋思想を相手にしていないでしょうけれども、上記のような問題群にどのように答えるかと私が想像してみると、おそらく次のようになるかと思います。つまり、パネンベルクは、ヘーゲルのように、存在と思想を同一のものとみなし、弁証法的に同一性へ帰る道をたどるでしょう(『精神現象学』参照)。東洋の人々が考える「心」は、西洋の人々が考えるそれとはいくぶん違っていて、相互にすれ違っていることがある、と。東洋の場合は、心というものを、人間の内面性全体の統合的機構として語っており、それをきっちり理性、意志、感情としては整理分類などしない。むしろこれらのものはすべて一つの大きな直感の中に総括される。
さて、(以下私のコメント)伝統的なスコラ思想の理性、意志、感性のきめ細かな分類法には、確かに長所もあれば短所もある。しかしまた、その区別を行わなかったとしても、究極的にかならずしもよりよい結果がもたらされるというわけでもない。少なくとも伝統的な分類の長所・短所をきちんと吟味すべきではないか。今、東洋では西洋的な技術主義と伝統的な神秘主義が不安定ながら共存しており、その伝統的な精神形態の支えもなく、またそれはそのまま続くことは望むべきものでもないであろう。というのは、にわかのそして容赦のない歴史の流れによってその伝統から引き出された東洋の人々も、物質主義と技術至上主義といういま一つの極端に陥らないように心すべきであろう。極端がいま一つの極論を呼ぶことはドイツ観念論哲学の後に、非常に荒削りな唯物論が続いたことでもよくわかるとおりである。
人格のほかに、人間学に深くかかわるテーマとして、たとえば「人権」とか、「自然法」とかをとりあげてみても、多分同じ問題にぶつかりそうだと思います。